Wednesday, January 21, 2009

The rhetoric of the absolute

As of late I have been reading Walter Brueggemann's "Theology of the Old Testament: Testimony, Dispute, Advocacy." However, this morning something really annoyed me, a tendency in much post-Derridean critical thinking. Following Derrida's critique of people like Heidegger, Plato, and Hegel, thinkers sometimes bring out a rather simplified picture of "totalizing" and "absolutizing" picture of western thought. In my view, this is tremendously wrong: not just because it over-generalizes in its own way, but rather because it seriously misreads so much of western philosophy. Derrida's deconstruction, I would argue, is quite egregious in this. 

First Brueggemann. In explaining the concept of "countertestimony" in the Old Testament (i.e., those texts of the Old Testament that seem to challenge Yahweh's sovereignty), Brueggemann sets up the opposition between a "Jewish" way of thinking, and a "mode of reason" associated with the West, "rooted in Plato", which tries to settle all disputes, and hence "to stop the political discourse that was sponsored by the Sophists" (330). What Brueggemann is pointing to here is the difference between "eristics" and "dialectics" for Plato. E.g., in the Meno, Socrates contrasts the "contentious and eristical wise men" to a more "gentle" form of discourse, "dialectic" (75d). For Brueggemann, and I would add a number of other contemporary Biblical scholars (Elisabeth Schüssler-Fiorenza comes to mind here), this is a contrast between an "open" rhetoric and sophistical movement, with a "closed" philosophical and absolutizing movement. Derrida certainly was fond of pointing to the chinks in the supposed armor of Platonic "realism." 

But is this what goes on in Plato? Hardly. One of the most consistent mistakes in understanding Plato is forgetting that he wrote dialogues, and that "Plato" never appears in any one of them. There is a good reason for this: Plato's Academy, as many attest to later (especially Cicero), was actually the most open of all the ancient philosophical schools (especially in comparison with the Epicureans), because so much of their philosophical way of life was rooted in dialectic. Dialectic is a communal process that philosophers in Plato's school engaged in, and it was primarily an askesis, or a self-transformative practice, that aimed at enabling the student to transform him or herself into one that submitted to reasonable discourse, instead of "eristics" - which in their view, was argument for argument's sake. In other words, the point of dialectic was to transform individuals into those who could recognize that force of the better argument, and participate in argumentation in order to search for the truth. 

Furthermore, it is clear from later dialogues such as the Parmenides (which is a thorough-going critique of the supposed "theory of forms") that there is no such thing as "Plato's doctrine" (written or, as the esoterics would have it, unwritten), and that the dialogues were not meant as a "system" of philosophy. From various testimonies in the Hellenistic period, Plato's Academy never had one over-arching "doctrine," like the Epicureans or Stoics (the Peripatos did not either), but included a multitude of perspectives. The philosophical way of life for Plato's Academy was thus philosophers learning how to dialogue with one another. I suspect it was rather the Imperial Period - especially the Neoplatonists - that codified a "Platonic" doctrine. This period was marked by commentary - which the earlier Hellenistic period was not.

Be that as it may, this brings up a tendency in contemporary thought, out of a somewhat Derridean lineage, to generalize certain aspects of a thinker without a seemingly clear interpretation of that thinker. Derrida, in my view, is the Socrates of the early dialogues. That Socrates asked the impossible: define "piety," "poetry," "virtue," etc. He was never asking to actually get a definition - the terms he sets up for this definition are too impossible by half - and so most of the early dialogues end in aporia, or in a puzzle. Derrida does this by looking at the impossible in texts, the little contradictions, the peculiarities, those parts of the text that seem to intentionally be misunderstood. He does this, it seems, for a very particular purpose: like Socrates, to engage us in active re-interpretation. Derrida is too, like Socrates, repetitive and annoying (Socrates himself mentions this fact in the Apology), and if you read too much Derrida, you start to be annoying. Nevertheless, Derrida's philosophical purpose seems to me to be right in line with the Academic (in the sense of Plato's school) way of thinking. Deconstruction is "justice," as Derrida says. In other words, deconstruction is a practice, an askesis that tries to move one out from under a self-satisfied "knowledge" of our philosophical tradition, toward a constant re-engagement with that tradition. 

The problem comes in with the "disciples" of the "deconstructionist." Too many thinkers take the easy way out, and refuse to deconstruct Derrida himself, or resort to the Pythagorean "ipse dixit" - Derrida tells us that Heidegger is absolutizing, Hegel is a totalist, Plato squashes all political debate. From the beginning though Derrida has always pointed to deconstruction as a method, like the Platonic dialectic, that does not issue into doctrines, but is an end in itself. Furthermore, the reason it is an end in itself is that it seems to me, at least, to be primarily a practice. Philosophy is a way of life, and like other thinkers before - the entire ancient tradition, but also thinkers like Wittgenstein, Hegel, and Heidegger - philosophy is meant to issue forth into an entire life. And as it was for Plato, so it is for Derrida: that life is a life of justice

1 comment:

Michael Ducey said...

Hi Austin,
I'm in NYC.
Site: www.thesecularspirit.com
Derrida was traumatized, dissociated.

Out-of-body Thinking

Derrida gets the language for his epistemology from Husserl. Phenomenology starts with a "principle of principles" that "primordial presence to intuition is the source of sense and evidence, the a priori of a prioris."

This means that "the certainty, itself ideal and absolute, that the universal form of all experience (Erlebnis), and therefore of all life, has always been and will always be the present. The present alone is and ever will be. Being is presence or the modification of presence. The relation with the presence of the present as the ultimate form of being and of ideality is the move by which I transgress empirical existence, factuality, contingency, worldliness, etc." [Speech and Phenomena, 53-54.]

However, the choice of the words "present" and "presence" to indicate the ground of all knowledge has some very unfortunate consequences. That choice sets up a confusion between two completely different meanings of the word "presence."

One meaning is "phenomenological presence". This refers to the immediate access to being in the original act of knowledge. It does not refer to time at all. So, phenomenological presence might be better expressed by calling it presence-to-being. That would save it from being confused with the other meaning of "presence", what we should call "temporal presence", that is, the occurrence of an event at a particular moment in time.

Derrida also calls this living presence "the now". This reinforces the confusion between presence-to-being and occurrence-at-a-particular-moment-in-time. It is also unfortunate that Derrida uses the word "form" in the phrase "the universal form of all experience". What he wants to refer to is the "universal basis of all experience", which is not a form. It is an act. But this word-slippage is also quite telling, and one of the many clues in Derrida's work that he is confusing the order of abstract concepts and the order of actual reality.

This epistemology leads to the cornerstone mistake of claiming that iterability is an a priori condition of knowing, whereas in fact iterability is an a posteriori result of knowing. An original presence-to-being (insight) occurs in time. Consequently it is repeatable. So, iterability is not "inside" phenomenological presence, it is extrinsic to it. This mistake is made all the more easy since both relationships are necessary. Once you get this, then all of Derrida's objections to realist epistemology collapse, and his whole philosophical system collapses into imaginary ashes.

I have discussed these issues at length in my article "Dealing With Derrida", which you can find on the Radical Academy web site. http://radicalacademy.com/studentrefphilmhd1.htm

Although running down Derrida's mistakes in his text is difficult, once you get the key point that he was dissociated, the whole pattern of his out-of-body thinking makes sense. Once you discover Derrida's dissociation, you find it in many thinkers. There is a lot of out-of-body thinking in philosophy and social theory. Perhaps leaving one's body is an occupational hazard for professional thinkers. Dissociation is the result of trauma, and trauma is easy to come by.

There are many sources of insight into dissociation. I recommend Trauma and the Body (2006) by Pat Ogden et al. as a start.